Crisis, What crisis?
Physics at the end of the Nineteenth Century.
John Pulham, Department of Mathematical Sciences, University of
Aberdeen
A Smug Professor
I’ll start with a quotation which, though possibly
apocryphal, well illustrates the common attitude to the state of the
Physical Sciences at the end of the nineteenth century. It was part of an
address by the Professor of Physics at Chicago on the occasion of the
opening of the Ryerson Physical Laboratory in 1894.
“The more important fundamental laws and facts
of the physical science have all been discovered, and these are now so
firmly established that the possibility of their ever being supplanted in
consequence of new discoveries is exceedingly remote....
Our future discoveries must be looked for in the sixth place of decimals.”
This ‘grand theory of everything’, that so
impressed people at the end of the nineteenth century, had two major
components. The first was Newton’s theory of Mechanics with its attendant
theory of Gravity. The second was the theory of Electricity and Magnetism.
Between them they seemed to give an adequate description of the known
phenomena of the physical world. Of course, not everything was known and not
all anomalies had been tidied up, but that seemed just a matter of time and
effort. As the quotation suggests, all fundamental laws were settled.
Newton
"Taking mathematics from the beginning of the
world to the time when Newton lived, what he has done is much the better
part."
- Leibniz
"The Principia is pre-eminent above any other
production of human genius."
- Laplace
"Nature and Nature's laws lay hid in night: God said, Let Newton be! and
all was light."
- Pope
Scattering ‘famous quotations’ through a document
is usually a way to avoid work. These three quotations, however, are there
for a purpose. They are clearly extreme in their praise of Newton. Were
these writers Cambridge sycophants worshiping at the shrine of correct
Newton thought?
Leibniz was a great philosopher and mathematician,
a contemporary of Newton and a Saxon. Because of a long priority dispute
over the Calculus, he had every reason to dislike and belittle Newton. He
did not.
Laplace was a major French Mathematician of the
late 18th Century and Newton’s achievement had been to dismiss French
Cartesian thinking. The French ought not to have been pleased (and Voltaire
had to do a lot of persuading).
Pope was neither a mathematician nor a scientist.
In 1686
Isaac
Newton published a book on the motion of bodies, the theory of gravity and
the System of the World. The book is now
known simply as the
Principia, and its publication
was the most important single event in the
history of science.
Newton provided science with four things: a
description of how bodies move under the action of forces, the general and
universal theory of gravity, the mathematics with which to handle these
theories and, finally, a new vision of the physical universe as a mechanism.
(There was the Optics as well, of course.)
These four achievements were of fundamental
significance not only in understanding the World but also in changing it.
Newton is the father of Engineering and the Industrial Revolution as much as
of Physical Science and scientific methodology.
For the next 200 years all developments in
Mechanics and most of those in Mathematics were based on Newton's
principles. They are the principles that I adopt when I teach mechanics to
our Engineering students in 2005.
The Eighteenth century saw great advances in the
application of Newton's ideas to the motion of solid bodies and of fluids
and gases, all critical for the development of engineering. After all, a
motor car is just a device that ignites a compressed mixture of gas and air
thus causing an explosion that forces a piston to move, in turn causing the
engine shaft to rotate. Everything about the mechanical (as opposed to
fashionable) design of a motor car is either Newtonian theory or empirical
result (and the empirical bits are just there because the theory is too
complicated to handle - not because the theory is felt to be inappropriate).
In the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries
Newton's mathematical methods were developed into even more powerful tools
for the analysis of physical processes.
The Apple and the Moon
"It was the rampart of God's house
That she was standing on;
By God built over the sheer depth
The which is Space begun;
So high, that looking downward thence
She scarce could see the sun.
It lies in Heaven, across the
flood
Of aether, as a bridge.
Beneath, the tides of day and night
With flame and darkness ridge
The void, as low as where this earth
Spins like a fretful midge".
Rossetti, from "The
Blessed Damozel"
There is a crucial feature of the Newtonian
development that needs comment. Before the scientific revolution of the
seventeenth century it was still largely the case that people
distinguished both practically and philosophically between 'down here' and
'up there' (my mum still does). In other words, the 'universe' was not
conceived of as an entity. There was no reason at all why the behaviour of
matter in the sublunary sphere should have any connection whatever with that
of spirit in the circles of heaven. (I know Rossetti wasn't 13th century, but he was
trying to be.) A large part of the objection to Copernicus' heliocentric
theory was that it seemed to contradict this division by mixing the Earth in
with the Upper Circle.
Newton, in comparing the motion of an apple and
that of the Moon is violating this basic distinction (he wasn't the first,
of course, but it is in his hands that the idea becomes solid). From
Newton's time onwards we have the notion of a cosmos, which 'contains
everything' and which is subject to uniform mathematical and scientific
laws.
This raised many questions about the nature of
this entity, not many of which were confidently answered in Newton's time.
Is the universe of finite or infinite extent? Which is the more ludicrous
proposition: that there are infinitely many stars or that there are only
finitely many of them?
Action at a Distance
Newton's law of gravity has a strange feature that
scandalised traditional thought at the time (particularly the French).
Newton says that a body A in one place exerts a certain force on a body B in
another place. It says nothing about how this force is conveyed from A to B,
other than that it is instantaneous. This is what is known as 'action at a
distance' and went violently against medieval ideas that there had to be
some 'intercessor' to convey the force. Actually, Newton rather agreed that
there had to be some such mechanism, but claimed that he didn't need to know
about it in order to formulate his theory. The Cartesians didn't think that
this was very logical and therefore didn't really understand what Newton
meant by saying that he had a 'theory'. This was a crucial change in the
philosophy of science, or perhaps a divorce of science from philosophy (but
wait until we get to electromagnetism!).
Electricity and Magnetism
Electricity and Magnetism were phenomena that had
been known for a very long time. In a sense they were much older than
Gravity as concepts. Before Newton there had been no real need for an
understanding of why things fell because that was what things did, as
everybody knew from infancy. Lightning and compass needles were more
mysterious and required explanation.
However, a theory of electricity and magnetism had
to wait until the end of the eighteenth century. This was partly because of
the technical difficulty and confusion of the subject and partly because of
the lack of an appropriate technology. It is difficult to study the
behaviour of electricity without a reliable source of electrical current,
and that had to wait on the development of such things as the electric
battery. Scientists do not live by thought alone.
From the late eighteenth century through to the
middle of the nineteenth huge advances were made in the understanding of
Electricity and Magnetism and, most importantly, their unsuspected
interactions. The early work of people like Cavendish and Coulomb led to the
work of people like Ampere, Gauss and Faraday. By the 1860s they had put
together a reasonably, though not fully, coherent theory of
electromagnetism.
Michael Faraday was an extraordinary figure. A
barely educated technician, with little mathematical training, he came to be
widely regarded as the greatest of all experimental physicists. Partly as a result of his lack of mathematics, Faraday was
forced to develop a mental 'picture' of the way in which electricity and
magnetism worked. In this picture electricity and magnetism became 'fields'
('tubes of force') that extended through space. In some ways this was a
return to Descartes' vortices and a distinct move away from ideas of action
at a distance. It was to become enormously influential in the later
development of the subject.
Maxwell and Radiation
"The special theory of relativity owes its
origins to Maxwell's equations of the electromagnetic field" — Albert
Einstein
James Clerk Maxwell was professor of Natural
Philosophy at Marischal College in Aberdeen from 1856 to 1860. This has to
be mentioned, because this is Aberdeen. This is also only a thirty minute
talk, so I will say no more about his short stay and abrupt departure.
Maxwell did many things in his short life, but his
real fame rests on three achievements.
Firstly, he brought about the final consolidation
of electricity and magnetism into a single self-consistent theory of
electromagnetism. This theory was summed up in a set of equations known ever
since as Maxwell's Equations.
Secondly, following Faraday's lead, he gave
increasing emphasis to the electric and magnetic fields as physical objects
with physical properties like energy and momentum.
Thirdly, he showed that his fundamental equations
predicted the existence of electromagnetic radiation (that is to say, the
electric and magnetic fields satisfied mathematical equations that, in other
contexts, would be seen as the equations governing oscillations and waves).
Furthermore, he conjectured that light was itself just another form of
electromagnetic radiation.
This all turned out to be quite useful. From it
come radio, television, mobile phones, X-ray machines, microwave cookers and
many other indispensable features of the modern economy. We already knew
about light.
Such was Maxwell's triumph that we need to be
reminded that his argument for his theory did not find universal
acceptance at the time. Figures as important as Lord Kelvin were sceptical
about it a couple of decades later. It is also true that Maxwell's
development of the theory had not fully analysed certain aspects of the
electrodynamics of moving bodies. These are some of the reasons why
theoreticians like
Lorentz were still actively developing EM theory thirty
years after Maxwell published his work.
The Speed of Light
A further comment needs to be made about Maxwell’s
identification of light as a form of electromagnetic radiation, in order to
explain some of the concerns that led to the theory of Relativity.
The ‘wave equation’ in electromagnetism that
predicts the existence of e.m. waves includes a constant, usually called
c, which represents the speed of propagation of the wave. When the
corresponding equation is applied to the vibration of a guitar string, this
‘constant’ depends on the nature and tension of the string and determines
the pitch of the sound produced by it. A guitarist tunes his string by
changing its tension and thus changing the value of c.
The interesting feature of Maxwell’s equations is
that the value of this constant c is non-negotiable. It is
constructed out of two of the fundamental universal constants that appear in
electromagnetic theory (e0
and m0) and has
an unambiguous value of about 186,300 miles per second.
Maxwell decided that light had to be a form of
electromagnetic radiation simply because this speed was (to within
experimental error) exactly the same as the measured speed of light—which
would be outrageous if it were only a coincidence.
The Aether
Maxwell's prediction of electromagnetic radiation,
and his claim that light was an example of such radiation, brought to a head
a problem that had been worrying people for ages, in many different ways.
Water waves are waves in water, sound waves are
waves in air. Maxwell now had waves of electromagnetism, but what was doing
the waving? Note that the result of the work of Faraday and Maxwell was to
make the electric and magnetic 'fields' into physical objects rather than
the mathematical abstractions that they had been in most other physicists'
work. You don't need anything to carry an abstraction, but you do need
something to carry a physical wave.
For a long time people had speculated about the 'luminiferous
aether'--the medium which carried light. To Maxwell, this had to be the same
thing, whatever it was, that carried his electromagnetic waves.
There were problems. You can see the stars at
night (sometimes). The stars are a long way away and, by common consent,
there is essentially 'nothing' between us and them. Interstellar space
counts as a vacuum. But we can still see the stars. So their light is coming
to us across this vacuum. So the 'vacuum' must be full of the aether. This is
puzzling. Almost as puzzling is the fact that I can see the stars though my
glasses, so there must be aether in my glasses. Just as dramatically I can
listen to the radio on my bedside set. The radio is picking up e.m. waves
transmitted by the BBC. My bed is surrounded by walls. So the walls must be
full of aether (though I can't see the stars through them).
At a more technical level the difficulties were
even more baffling. It became clear that a substance capable of vibrating in
the way required by Maxwell's theory had to have very strange physical
properties, most of them quite inconsistent with the idea of some tenuous
'gas' that managed to pervade everything.
(In this context it is worth pointing out that,
even though people like Maxwell were aware of 'atoms', it was to be decades
before scientists had any comfortable picture of the atomic or subatomic
world. We now know that 'solid' objects are almost entirely 'vacuum'. In
Maxwell's time there was still a clear distinction between 'solid matter'
and what was outside it. This further confused the theory of the aether.)
In view of these difficulties it should come as no
surprise that the late nineteenth century produced a veritable zoo of aether
theories.
This is physics, not philosophy, so the proper
reaction to such confusion is to do experiments (do lots of experiments!).
I will only mention one of these experiments here, because of its
significance for Einstein's work. There had been serious dispute as to
whether we (meaning the Earth) were moving through the aether (I was going to
say like a fish though water, but in this case the water goes through the
fish as well) or whether we dragged the aether along with us. Maxwell
certainly expected the aether within solid bodies to be at rest with respect
to the body and other physicists had even more complicated pictures.
This seems to be an obvious candidate for an
experiment. Would it be possible, in some way to measure the motion of the
Earth through the aether? The Polish-American physicist
Albert Michelson
argued that if there were such a motion then the speed of light, as measured
by somebody on the Earth, would be different in different directions. He was
led to the idea of his experiment by the age-old problem of rowing a boat
across a flowing river.
John Reid will deal with the experiment in his
talk, so I will not go into any details about it here. Let me just report
the result: Michelson, and his collaborator Morley, could find no evidence
of any motion relative to any aether.
That was a useful result because it ruled out one
class of aether theories. Unfortunately for the composure of physicists, the
remaining theories had mostly been discredited for other reasons. So there
were no plausible theories left!
This was a pity because, as J. J. Thomson was to
say in 1906 (note the date), "The aether is not a fantastic creation of the speculative
philosopher; it is as essential to us as the air we breath".
Desperate circumstances call for desperate
remedies and such a remedy was soon forthcoming. The Irish physicist
Fitzgerald proposed a solution which was later given a slightly more
respectable form by the Dutch physicist Hendrik Lorentz in his version of
electromagnetic theory. It turned out that you could wriggle out of the
results of Michelson' s experiment by assuming that a body, moving into the
'aether wind', was ever so slightly shortened by the experience. This, if the
formulas were rigged carefully, would have the effect of counteracting the
change in the speed of light and explaining the null result of the
experiment. Make of that what you will. It wasn't really any more ridiculous
than most of the other aether theories.
The End of the Century
Industry was in full swing. Iron ships sailed the
seas, railways spread over the earth, wireless telegraphy was just starting,
London was about to build its first electricity generating station,
chemistry had come of age with a welter of industrial processes, the motions
of the planets were known with unprecedented accuracy, the inner structure
of the atom was about to be probed. All was good.
Except for that damned aether, which wouldn't
behave and wouldn't go away.
Which brings us back to the start of the talk.
That optimistic professor of Physics in Chicago was none other than Albert
Michelson (after his experiment). Within a decade the problems that
he and Lorentz had puzzled over led another Albert to ask a few simple
questions, and the world was changed forever.
(P.S. ether vs. ćther: The OED has aether
as 'archaic', which would be news to Maxwell, who hasn't been dead that
long.)
(P.P.S. What's the difference between a
mathematician and a physicist?:
"An engineer, a physicist and a
mathematician were travelling by train in Australia when they saw a sheep.
'Hey look, the sheep in Australia are black', said the engineer.
'No! All we can say is that at least one sheep in Australia is
black', said the physicist.
'Nonsense!', said the mathematician, 'There is at least one sheep in
Australia, at least one side of which is black'."
A mathematician sees this as a joke
against physicists. A physicist sees it as a joke against mathematicians.
Engineers know that it is a joke against them. It brings out nicely the
difference between reason and logic. )
Home Page
"Einstein's 1905 Paper on Relativity"
"Experimental Tests of Special Relativity"
|